Utility, Substitution and Demand
2: Utility
In general, if my current choice is A, I might change to
alternative B if:
-
A becomes more difficult
-
B becomes easy (fewer costs associated with it)
-
the rewards of A are less appealing
-
the rewards of B become more appealing
-
an undesirable consequence of A becomes more likely (subjectively
probable)
-
a desirable consequence of A becomes less likely
-
a desirable consequence of B becomes more likely
-
...and so on
Spelt out at length, this becomes a mess. We would like to express all
of this in one go, and this is where we bring in the other microeconomic
topic: utility.
Utility is just a numerical comparative measure of the subjective desirability
of something. By "comparative" I mean that a utility on its own has no
meaning: the numbers are only useful as a basis for comparing different
options. Saying that there are only three options, whose utilities are
1, 2 and 3, is in effect the same as saying that their utilities are 101,
102 and 103, or for that matter 0.1, 0.2 and 0.3.
The decision principle that goes with this is the Maximisation
of Subjective Expected Utility:
-
"maximisation" because, for a choice between some set of acts, the one
chosen has the highest utility
-
"subjective" because the choice depends on the decision-maker's preferences
and beliefs, not on reality (hence the economic viability of a whole industry
of advertising, which improves subjective perceptions of a product without
improving the product)
-
"expected" because utilities are calculated using the expectation principle;
in other words the utility of an act is a weighted sum of the utilities
of all the possible consequences, with the most likely consequences getting
the strongest weighting.
Now let's apply this to a specific choice.
INDEX | 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 | NEXT